TacticsMore Basic Tactics

This chapter introduces several more proof strategies and tactics that allow us to prove more interesting properties of functional programs. We will see:
  • how to use auxiliary lemmas in both "forward-style" and "backward-style" proofs;
  • how to reason about data constructors (in particular, how to use the fact that they are injective and disjoint);
  • how to create a strong induction hypothesis (and when such strengthening is required); and
  • more details on how to reason by case analysis.

Require Export Poly.

The apply Tactic

We often encounter situations where the goal to be proved is exactly the same as some hypothesis in the context or some previously proved lemma.

Theorem silly1 : (n m o p : nat),
     n = m
     [n;o] = [n;p]
     [n;o] = [m;p].
Proof.
  intros n m o p eq1 eq2.
  rewrite eq1.

At this point, we could finish with "rewrite eq2. reflexivity." as we have done several times before. We can achieve the same effect in a single step by using the apply tactic instead:

  apply eq2. Qed.

The apply tactic also works with conditional hypotheses and lemmas: if the statement being applied is an implication, then the premises of this implication will be added to the list of subgoals needing to be proved.

Theorem silly2 : (n m o p : nat),
     n = m
     ((q r : nat), q = r [q;o] = [r;p])
     [n;o] = [m;p].
Proof.
  intros n m o p eq1 eq2.
  apply eq2. apply eq1. Qed.

You may find it instructive to experiment with this proof and see if there is a way to complete it using just rewrite instead of apply.
Typically, when we use apply H, the statement H will begin with a that binds some universal variables. When Coq matches the current goal against the conclusion of H, it will try to find appropriate values for these variables. For example, when we do apply eq2 in the following proof, the universal variable q in eq2 gets instantiated with n and r gets instantiated with m.

Theorem silly2a : (n m : nat),
     (n,n) = (m,m)
     ((q r : nat), (q,q) = (r,r) [q] = [r])
     [n] = [m].
Proof.
  intros n m eq1 eq2.
  apply eq2. apply eq1. Qed.

Exercise: 2 stars, optional (silly_ex)

Complete the following proof without using simpl.

Theorem silly_ex :
     (n, evenb n = true oddb (S n) = true)
     evenb 3 = true
     oddb 4 = true.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
To use the apply tactic, the (conclusion of the) fact being applied must match the goal exactly — for example, apply will not work if the left and right sides of the equality are swapped.

Theorem silly3_firsttry : (n : nat),
     true = beq_nat n 5
     beq_nat (S (S n)) 7 = true.
Proof.
  intros n H.
  simpl.
  (* Here we cannot use apply directly *)
Abort.

In this case we can use the symmetry tactic, which switches the left and right sides of an equality in the goal.

Theorem silly3 : (n : nat),
     true = beq_nat n 5
     beq_nat (S (S n)) 7 = true.
Proof.
  intros n H.
  symmetry.
  simpl. (* Actually, this simpl is unnecessary, since
            apply will perform simplification first. *)

  apply H. Qed.

Exercise: 3 stars (apply_exercise1)

(Hint: You can use apply with previously defined lemmas, not just hypotheses in the context. Remember that SearchAbout is your friend.)

Theorem rev_exercise1 : (l l' : list nat),
     l = rev l'
     l' = rev l.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 1 star, optional (apply_rewrite)

Briefly explain the difference between the tactics apply and rewrite. What are the situations where both can usefully be applied?
(* FILL IN HERE *)

The apply ... with ... Tactic

The following silly example uses two rewrites in a row to get from [a,b] to [e,f].

Example trans_eq_example : (a b c d e f : nat),
     [a;b] = [c;d]
     [c;d] = [e;f]
     [a;b] = [e;f].
Proof.
  intros a b c d e f eq1 eq2.
  rewrite eq1. rewrite eq2. reflexivity. Qed.

Since this is a common pattern, we might like to pull it out as a lemma recording, once and for all, the fact that equality is transitive.

Theorem trans_eq : (X:Type) (n m o : X),
  n = m m = o n = o.
Proof.
  intros X n m o eq1 eq2. rewrite eq1. rewrite eq2.
  reflexivity. Qed.

Now, we should be able to use trans_eq to prove the above example. However, to do this we need a slight refinement of the apply tactic.

Example trans_eq_example' : (a b c d e f : nat),
     [a;b] = [c;d]
     [c;d] = [e;f]
     [a;b] = [e;f].
Proof.
  intros a b c d e f eq1 eq2.

If we simply tell Coq apply trans_eq at this point, it can tell (by matching the goal against the conclusion of the lemma) that it should instantiate X with [nat], n with [a,b], and o with [e,f]. However, the matching process doesn't determine an instantiation for m: we have to supply one explicitly by adding with (m:=[c,d]) to the invocation of apply.

  apply trans_eq with (m:=[c;d]). apply eq1. apply eq2. Qed.

Actually, we usually don't have to include the name m in the with clause; Coq is often smart enough to figure out which instantiation we're giving. We could instead write: apply trans_eq with [c;d].

Exercise: 3 stars, optional (apply_with_exercise)

Example trans_eq_exercise : (n m o p : nat),
     m = (minustwo o)
     (n + p) = m
     (n + p) = (minustwo o).
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

The inversion Tactic

Recall the definition of natural numbers:
     Inductive nat : Type :=
       | O : nat
       | S : nat  nat.
It is obvious from this definition that every number has one of two forms: either it is the constructor O or it is built by applying the constructor S to another number. But there is more here than meets the eye: implicit in the definition (and in our informal understanding of how datatype declarations work in other programming languages) are two more facts:
  • The constructor S is injective. That is, if S n = S m, it must be the case that n = m.
  • The constructors O and S are disjoint. That is, O is not equal to S n for any n.
Similar principles apply to all inductively defined types: all constructors are injective, and the values built from distinct constructors are never equal. For lists, the cons constructor is injective and nil is different from every non-empty list. For booleans, true and false are different. (Since neither true nor false take any arguments, their injectivity is not an issue.) And so on.
Coq provides a tactic called inversion that allows us to exploit these principles in proofs. To see how to use it, let's show explicitly that the S constructor is injective:

Theorem S_injective : (n m : nat),
  S n = S m
  n = m.
Proof.
  intros n m H.

By writing inversion H at this point, we ask Coq to generate all equations that it can infer from H as additional hypotheses, replacing variables in the goal as it goes. In the present example, this amounts to adding a new hypothesis H1 : n = m and replacing n by m in the goal.

  inversion H. reflexivity. Qed.

Here's a more interesting example that shows how multiple equations can be derived at once.

Theorem inversion_ex1 : (n m o : nat),
  [n; m] = [o; o]
  [n] = [m].
Proof.
  intros n m o H. inversion H. reflexivity. Qed.

It is possible to name the equations that inversion generates with an as ... clause:

Theorem inversion_ex2 : (n m : nat),
  [n] = [m]
  n = m.
Proof.
  intros n o H. inversion H as [Hno]. reflexivity. Qed.

Exercise: 1 star (inversion_ex3)

Example inversion_ex3 : (X : Type) (x y z : X) (l j : list X),
  x :: y :: l = z :: j
  y :: l = x :: j
  x = y.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
While the injectivity of constructors allows us to reason that (n m : nat), S n = S m n = m, the converse of this implication is an instance of a more general fact about constructors and functions, which we will find useful below:

Theorem f_equal : (A B : Type) (f: A B) (x y: A),
  x = y f x = f y.
Proof. intros A B f x y eq. rewrite eq. reflexivity. Qed.

When used on a hypothesis involving an equality between different constructors (e.g., S n = O), inversion solves the goal immediately. To see why this makes sense, consider the following proof:

Theorem beq_nat_0_l : n,
   beq_nat 0 n = true n = 0.
Proof.
  intros n.

We can proceed by case analysis on n. The first case is trivial.

  destruct n as [| n'].
  - (* n = 0 *)
    intros H. reflexivity.

However, the second one doesn't look so simple: assuming beq_nat 0 (S n') = true, we must show S n' = 0, but the latter clearly contradictory! The way forward lies in the assumption. After simplifying the goal state, we see that beq_nat 0 (S n') = true has become false = true:

  - (* n = S n' *)
    simpl.

If we use inversion on this hypothesis, Coq notices that the subgoal we are working on is impossible, and therefore removes it from further consideration.

    intros H. inversion H. Qed.

This is an instance of a general logical principle known as the principle of explosion, which asserts that a contradiction entails anything, even false things. For instance:

Theorem inversion_ex4 : (n : nat),
  S n = O
  2 + 2 = 5.
Proof.
  intros n contra. inversion contra. Qed.

Theorem inversion_ex5 : (n m : nat),
  false = true
  [n] = [m].
Proof.
  intros n m contra. inversion contra. Qed.

If you find the principle of explosion confusing, remember that these proofs are not actually showing that the conclusion of the statement holds. Rather, they are arguing that the situation described by the premise can never arise, so the implication is vacuous. We'll explore the principle of explosion of more detail in the next chapter.

Exercise: 1 star (inversion_ex6)

Example inversion_ex6 : (X : Type)
                          (x y z : X) (l j : list X),
  x :: y :: l = []
  y :: l = z :: j
  x = z.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
To summarize this discussion, suppose H is a hypothesis in the context or a previously proven lemma of the form
      c a1 a2 ... an = d b1 b2 ... bm
for some constructors c and d and arguments a1 ... an and b1 ... bm. Then inversion H has the following effect:
  • If c and d are the same constructor, then, by the injectivity of this constructor, we know that a1 = b1, a2 = b2, etc.; inversion H adds these facts to the context, and tries to use them to rewrite the goal.
  • If c and d are different constructors, then the hypothesis H is contradictory, and the current goal doesn't have to be considered. In this case, inversion H marks the current goal as completed and pops it off the goal stack.

Using Tactics on Hypotheses

By default, most tactics work on the goal formula and leave the context unchanged. However, most tactics also have a variant that performs a similar operation on a statement in the context.
For example, the tactic simpl in H performs simplification in the hypothesis named H in the context.

Theorem S_inj : (n m : nat) (b : bool),
     beq_nat (S n) (S m) = b
     beq_nat n m = b.
Proof.
  intros n m b H. simpl in H. apply H. Qed.

Similarly, apply L in H matches some conditional statement L (of the form L1 L2, say) against a hypothesis H in the context. However, unlike ordinary apply (which rewrites a goal matching L2 into a subgoal L1), apply L in H matches H against L1 and, if successful, replaces it with L2.
In other words, apply L in H gives us a form of "forward reasoning": from L1 L2 and a hypothesis matching L1, it produces a hypothesis matching L2. By contrast, apply L is "backward reasoning": it says that if we know L1L2 and we are trying to prove L2, it suffices to prove L1.
Here is a variant of a proof from above, using forward reasoning throughout instead of backward reasoning.

Theorem silly3' : (n : nat),
  (beq_nat n 5 = true beq_nat (S (S n)) 7 = true)
  true = beq_nat n 5
  true = beq_nat (S (S n)) 7.
Proof.
  intros n eq H.
  symmetry in H. apply eq in H. symmetry in H.
  apply H. Qed.

Forward reasoning starts from what is given (premises, previously proven theorems) and iteratively draws conclusions from them until the goal is reached. Backward reasoning starts from the goal, and iteratively reasons about what would imply the goal, until premises or previously proven theorems are reached. If you've seen informal proofs before (for example, in a math or computer science class), they probably used forward reasoning. In general, idiomatic use of Coq tends to favor backward reasoning, but in some situations the forward style can be easier to think about.

Exercise: 3 stars, recommended (plus_n_n_injective)

Practice using "in" variants in this exercise. (Hint: use plus_n_Sm.)

Theorem plus_n_n_injective : n m,
     n + n = m + m
     n = m.
Proof.
  intros n. induction n as [| n'].
    (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Varying the Induction Hypothesis

Sometimes it is important to control the exact form of the induction hypothesis when carrying out inductive proofs in Coq. In particular, we need to be careful about which of the assumptions we move (using intros) from the goal to the context before invoking the induction tactic. For example, suppose we want to show that the double function is injective — i.e., that it always maps different arguments to different results:
    Theorem double_injectiven m
      double n = double m  n = m.
The way we start this proof is a bit delicate: if we begin with
      intros n. induction n.
all is well. But if we begin it with
      intros n m. induction n.
we get stuck in the middle of the inductive case...

Theorem double_injective_FAILED : n m,
     double n = double m
     n = m.
Proof.
  intros n m. induction n as [| n'].
  - (* n = O *) simpl. intros eq. destruct m as [| m'].
    + (* m = O *) reflexivity.
    + (* m = S m' *) inversion eq.
  - (* n = S n' *) intros eq. destruct m as [| m'].
    + (* m = O *) inversion eq.
    + (* m = S m' *) apply f_equal.

At this point, the induction hypothesis, IHn', does not give us n' = m' — there is an extra S in the way — so the goal is not provable.

      Abort.

What went wrong?
The problem is that, at the point we invoke the induction hypothesis, we have already introduced m into the context — intuitively, we have told Coq, "Let's consider some particular n and m..." and we now have to prove that, if double n = double m for these particular n and m, then n = m.
The next tactic, induction n says to Coq: We are going to show the goal by induction on n. That is, we are going to prove, for all n, that the proposition
  • P n = "if double n = double m, then n = m"
holds, by showing
  • P O
    (i.e., "if double O = double m then O = m") and
  • P n P (S n)
    (i.e., "if double n = double m then n = m" implies "if double (S n) = double m then S n = m").
If we look closely at the second statement, it is saying something rather strange: it says that, for a particular m, if we know
  • "if double n = double m then n = m"
then we can prove
  • "if double (S n) = double m then S n = m".
To see why this is strange, let's think of a particular m — say, 5. The statement is then saying that, if we know
  • Q = "if double n = 10 then n = 5"
then we can prove
  • R = "if double (S n) = 10 then S n = 5".
But knowing Q doesn't give us any help at all with proving R! (If we tried to prove R from Q, we would start with something like "Suppose double (S n) = 10..." but then we'd be stuck: knowing that double (S n) is 10 tells us nothing about whether double n is 10, so Q is useless.)
To summarize: Trying to carry out this proof by induction on n when m is already in the context doesn't work because we are then trying to prove a relation involving every n but just a single m.
The good proof of double_injective leaves m in the goal statement at the point where the induction tactic is invoked on n:

Theorem double_injective : n m,
     double n = double m
     n = m.
Proof.
  intros n. induction n as [| n'].
  - (* n = O *) simpl. intros m eq. destruct m as [| m'].
    + (* m = O *) reflexivity.
    + (* m = S m' *) inversion eq.

  - (* n = S n' *) simpl.

Notice that both the goal and the induction hypothesis are different this time: the goal asks us to prove something more general (i.e., to prove the statement for every m), but the IH is correspondingly more flexible, allowing us to choose any m we like when we apply the IH.

    intros m eq.

Now we've chosen a particular m and introduced the assumption that double n = double m. Since we are doing a case analysis on n, we also need a case analysis on m to keep the two "in sync."

    destruct m as [| m'].
    + (* m = O *) simpl.

The 0 case is trivial:

      inversion eq.

    + (* m = S m' *)
      apply f_equal.

At this point, since we are in the second branch of the destruct m, the m' mentioned in the context is the predecessor of the m we started out talking about. Since we are also in the S branch of the induction, this is perfect: if we instantiate the generic m in the IH with the current m' (this instantiation is performed automatically by the apply in the next step), then IHn' gives us exactly what we need to finish the proof.

      apply IHn'. inversion eq. reflexivity. Qed.

What you should take away from all this is that we need to be careful about using induction to try to prove something too specific: If we're proving a property of n and m by induction on n, we may need to leave m generic.
The following exercise requires the same pattern.

Exercise: 2 stars (beq_nat_true)

Theorem beq_nat_true : n m,
    beq_nat n m = true n = m.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 2 stars, advanced (beq_nat_true_informal)

Give a careful informal proof of beq_nat_true, being as explicit as possible about quantifiers.

(* FILL IN HERE *)
The strategy of doing fewer intros before an induction to obtain a more general IH doesn't always work by itself; sometimes a little rearrangement of quantified variables is needed. Suppose, for example, that we wanted to prove double_injective by induction on m instead of n.

Theorem double_injective_take2_FAILED : n m,
     double n = double m
     n = m.
Proof.
  intros n m. induction m as [| m'].
  - (* m = O *) simpl. intros eq. destruct n as [| n'].
    + (* n = O *) reflexivity.
    + (* n = S n' *) inversion eq.
  - (* m = S m' *) intros eq. destruct n as [| n'].
    + (* n = O *) inversion eq.
    + (* n = S n' *) apply f_equal.
        (* Stuck again here, just like before. *)
Abort.

The problem here is that, to do induction on m, we must first introduce n. (If we simply say induction m without introducing anything first, Coq will automatically introduce n for us!)
What can we do about this? One possibility is to rewrite the statement of the lemma so that m is quantified before n. This will work, but it's not nice: We don't want to have to twist the statements of lemmas to fit the needs of a particular strategy for proving them — we want to state them in the most clear and natural way.
What we can do instead is to first introduce all the quantified variables and then re-generalize one or more of them, selectively taking variables out of the context and putting them back at the beginning of the goal. The generalize dependent tactic does this.

Theorem double_injective_take2 : n m,
     double n = double m
     n = m.
Proof.
  intros n m.
  (* n and m are both in the context *)
  generalize dependent n.
  (* Now n is back in the goal and we can do induction on
     m and get a sufficiently general IH. *)

  induction m as [| m'].
  - (* m = O *) simpl. intros n eq. destruct n as [| n'].
    + (* n = O *) reflexivity.
    + (* n = S n' *) inversion eq.
  - (* m = S m' *) intros n eq. destruct n as [| n'].
    + (* n = O *) inversion eq.
    + (* n = S n' *) apply f_equal.
      apply IHm'. inversion eq. reflexivity. Qed.

Let's look at an informal proof of this theorem. Note that the proposition we prove by induction leaves n quantified, corresponding to the use of generalize dependent in our formal proof.
Theorem: For any nats n and m, if double n = double m, then n = m.
Proof: Let m be a nat. We prove by induction on m that, for any n, if double n = double m then n = m.
  • First, suppose m = 0, and suppose n is a number such that double n = double m. We must show that n = 0.
    Since m = 0, by the definition of double we have double n = 0. There are two cases to consider for n. If n = 0 we are done, since m = 0 = n, as required. Otherwise, if n = S n' for some n', we derive a contradiction: by the definition of double, we can calculate double n = S (S (double n')), but this contradicts the assumption that double n = 0.
  • Second, suppose m = S m' and that n is again a number such that double n = double m. We must show that n = S m', with the induction hypothesis that for every number s, if double s = double m' then s = m'.
    By the fact that m = S m' and the definition of double, we have double n = S (S (double m')). There are two cases to consider for n.
    If n = 0, then by definition double n = 0, a contradiction.
    Thus, we may assume that n = S n' for some n', and again by the definition of double we have S (S (double n')) = S (S (double m')), which implies by inversion that double n' = double m'. Instantiating the induction hypothesis with n' thus allows us to conclude that n' = m', and it follows immediately that S n' = S m'. Since S n' = n and S m' = m, this is just what we wanted to show.
Before we close this section and move on to some exercises, let's digress briefly and use beq_nat_true to prove a similar property about identifiers that we'll need in later chapters:

Theorem beq_id_true : x y,
  beq_id x y = true x = y.
Proof.
  intros [m] [n]. simpl. intros H.
  assert (H' : m = n). { apply beq_nat_true. apply H. }
  rewrite H'. reflexivity.
Qed.

Exercise: 3 stars, recommended (gen_dep_practice)

Prove this by induction on l.

Theorem nth_error_after_last: (n : nat) (X : Type) (l : list X),
     length l = n
     nth_error l n = None.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 3 stars, optional (app_length_cons)

Prove this by induction on l1, without using app_length from Lists.

Theorem app_length_cons : (X : Type) (l1 l2 : list X)
                                  (x : X) (n : nat),
     length (l1 ++ (x :: l2)) = n
     S (length (l1 ++ l2)) = n.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 4 stars, optional (app_length_twice)

Prove this by induction on l, without using app_length from Lists.

Theorem app_length_twice : (X:Type) (n:nat) (l:list X),
     length l = n
     length (l ++ l) = n + n.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 3 stars, optional (double_induction)

Prove the following principle of induction over two naturals.

Theorem double_induction: (P : nat nat Prop),
  P 0 0
  (m, P m 0 P (S m) 0)
  (n, P 0 n P 0 (S n))
  (m n, P m n P (S m) (S n))
  m n, P m n.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Unfolding Definitions

It sometimes happens that we need to manually unfold a Definition so that we can manipulate its right-hand side. For example, if we define...

Definition square n := n * n.

... and try to prove a simple fact about square...

Lemma square_mult : n m, square (n * m) = square n * square m.
Proof.
  intros n m.
  simpl.

... we get stuck: simpl doesn't simplify anything at this point, and since we haven't proved any other facts about square, there is nothing we can apply or rewrite with.
To make progress, we can manually unfold the definition of square:

  unfold square.

Now we have plenty to work with: both sides of the equality are expressions involving multiplication, and we have lots of facts about multiplication at our disposal. In particular, we know that it is commutative and associative, and from these facts it is not hard to finish the proof.

  rewrite mult_assoc.
  assert (H : n * m * n = n * n * m).
  { rewrite mult_comm. apply mult_assoc. }
  rewrite H. rewrite mult_assoc. reflexivity.
Qed.

At this point, a deeper discussion of unfolding and simplification is in order.
You may already have observed that tactics like simpl, reflexivity, and apply will often unfold the definitions of functions automatically when it allows them to make progress. For example, if we define foo m to be the constant 5,

Definition foo (x: nat) := 5.

then the simpl in the following proof (or the reflexivity, if we omit the simpl) will unfold foo m to (fun x 5) m and then further simplify this expression to just 5.

Fact silly_fact_1 : m, foo m + 1 = foo (m + 1) + 1.
Proof.
  intros m.
  simpl.
  reflexivity.
Qed.

However, this automatic unfolding is rather conservative. For example, if we define a slightly more complicated function involving a pattern match...

Definition bar x :=
  match x with
  | O ⇒ 5
  | S _ ⇒ 5
  end.

...then the analogous proof will get stuck:

Fact silly_fact_2_FAILED : m, bar m + 1 = bar (m + 1) + 1.
Proof.
  intros m.
  simpl. (* Does nothing! *)
Abort.

The reason that simpl doesn't make progress here is that it notices that, after tentatively unfolding bar m, it is left with a match whose scrutinee, m, is a variable, so the match cannot be simplified further. (It is not smart enough to notice that the two branches of the match are identical.) So it gives up on unfolding bar m and leaves it alone. Similarly, tentatively unfolding bar (m+1) leaves a match whose scrutinee is a function application (that, itself, cannot be simplified, even after unfolding the definition of +), so simpl leaves it alone.
At this point, there are two ways to make progress. One is to use destruct m to break the proof into two cases, each focusing on a more concrete choice of m (O vs S _). In each case, the match inside of bar can now make progress, and the proof is easy to complete.

Fact silly_fact_2 : m, bar m + 1 = bar (m + 1) + 1.
Proof.
  intros m.
  destruct m.
  - simpl. reflexivity.
  - simpl. reflexivity.
Qed.

This approach works, but it depends on our recognizing that the match hidden inside bar is what was preventing us from making progress.
A more straightforward way to finish the proof is to explicitly tell Coq to unfold bar.

Fact silly_fact_2' : m, bar m + 1 = bar (m + 1) + 1.
Proof.
  intros m.
  unfold bar.

Now it is apparent that we are stuck on the match expressions on both sides of the =, and we can use destruct to finish the proof without thinking too hard.

  destruct m.
  - reflexivity.
  - reflexivity.
Qed.

Using destruct on Compound Expressions

We have seen many examples where destruct is used to perform case analysis of the value of some variable. But sometimes we need to reason by cases on the result of some expression. We can also do this with destruct.
Here are some examples:

Definition sillyfun (n : nat) : bool :=
  if beq_nat n 3 then false
  else if beq_nat n 5 then false
  else false.

Theorem sillyfun_false : (n : nat),
  sillyfun n = false.
Proof.
  intros n. unfold sillyfun.
  destruct (beq_nat n 3).
    - (* beq_nat n 3 = true *) reflexivity.
    - (* beq_nat n 3 = false *) destruct (beq_nat n 5).
      + (* beq_nat n 5 = true *) reflexivity.
      + (* beq_nat n 5 = false *) reflexivity. Qed.

After unfolding sillyfun in the above proof, we find that we are stuck on if (beq_nat n 3) then ... else .... But either n is equal to 3 or it isn't, so we can use destruct (beq_nat n 3) to let us reason about the two cases.
In general, the destruct tactic can be used to perform case analysis of the results of arbitrary computations. If e is an expression whose type is some inductively defined type T, then, for each constructor c of T, destruct e generates a subgoal in which all occurrences of e (in the goal and in the context) are replaced by c.

Exercise: 3 stars, optional (combine_split)

Theorem combine_split : X Y (l : list (X * Y)) l1 l2,
  split l = (l1, l2)
  combine l1 l2 = l.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
However, destructing compound expressions requires a bit of care, as such destructs can sometimes erase information we need to complete a proof. For example, suppose we define a function sillyfun1 like this:

Definition sillyfun1 (n : nat) : bool :=
  if beq_nat n 3 then true
  else if beq_nat n 5 then true
  else false.

Now suppose that we want to convince Coq of the (rather obvious) fact that sillyfun1 n yields true only when n is odd. By analogy with the proofs we did with sillyfun above, it is natural to start the proof like this:

Theorem sillyfun1_odd_FAILED : (n : nat),
     sillyfun1 n = true
     oddb n = true.
Proof.
  intros n eq. unfold sillyfun1 in eq.
  destruct (beq_nat n 3).
  (* stuck... *)
Abort.

We get stuck at this point because the context does not contain enough information to prove the goal! The problem is that the substitution performed by destruct is too brutal — it threw away every occurrence of beq_nat n 3, but we need to keep some memory of this expression and how it was destructed, because we need to be able to reason that, since beq_nat n 3 = true in this branch of the case analysis, it must be that n = 3, from which it follows that n is odd.
What we would really like is to substitute away all existing occurences of beq_nat n 3, but at the same time add an equation to the context that records which case we are in. The eqn: qualifier allows us to introduce such an equation, giving it a name that we choose.

Theorem sillyfun1_odd : (n : nat),
     sillyfun1 n = true
     oddb n = true.
Proof.
  intros n eq. unfold sillyfun1 in eq.
  destruct (beq_nat n 3) eqn:Heqe3.
  (* Now we have the same state as at the point where we got
     stuck above, except that the context contains an extra
     equality assumption, which is exactly what we need to
     make progress. *)

    - (* e3 = true *) apply beq_nat_true in Heqe3.
      rewrite Heqe3. reflexivity.
    - (* e3 = false *)
     (* When we come to the second equality test in the body
        of the function we are reasoning about, we can use
        eqn: again in the same way, allow us to finish the
        proof. *)

      destruct (beq_nat n 5) eqn:Heqe5.
        + (* e5 = true *)
          apply beq_nat_true in Heqe5.
          rewrite Heqe5. reflexivity.
        + (* e5 = false *) inversion eq. Qed.

Exercise: 2 stars (destruct_eqn_practice)

Theorem bool_fn_applied_thrice :
  (f : bool bool) (b : bool),
  f (f (f b)) = f b.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Review

We've now seen many of Coq's most fundamental tactics. We'll introduce a few more in the coming chapters, and later on we'll see some more powerful automation tactics that make Coq help us with low-level details. But basically we've got what we need to get work done.
Here are the ones we've seen:
  • intros: move hypotheses/variables from goal to context
  • reflexivity: finish the proof (when the goal looks like e = e)
  • apply: prove goal using a hypothesis, lemma, or constructor
  • apply... in H: apply a hypothesis, lemma, or constructor to a hypothesis in the context (forward reasoning)
  • apply... with...: explicitly specify values for variables that cannot be determined by pattern matching
  • simpl: simplify computations in the goal
  • simpl in H: ... or a hypothesis
  • rewrite: use an equality hypothesis (or lemma) to rewrite the goal
  • rewrite ... in H: ... or a hypothesis
  • symmetry: changes a goal of the form t=u into u=t
  • symmetry in H: changes a hypothesis of the form t=u into u=t
  • unfold: replace a defined constant by its right-hand side in the goal
  • unfold... in H: ... or a hypothesis
  • destruct... as...: case analysis on values of inductively defined types
  • destruct... eqn:...: specify the name of an equation to be added to the context, recording the result of the case analysis
  • induction... as...: induction on values of inductively defined types
  • inversion: reason by injectivity and distinctness of constructors
  • assert (e) as H: introduce a "local lemma" e and call it H
  • generalize dependent x: move the variable x (and anything else that depends on it) from the context back to an explicit hypothesis in the goal formula

Additional Exercises

Exercise: 3 stars (beq_nat_sym)

Theorem beq_nat_sym : (n m : nat),
  beq_nat n m = beq_nat m n.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 3 stars, advanced, optional (beq_nat_sym_informal)

Give an informal proof of this lemma that corresponds to your formal proof above:
Theorem: For any nats n m, beq_nat n m = beq_nat m n.
Proof: (* FILL IN HERE *)

Exercise: 3 stars, optional (beq_nat_trans)

Theorem beq_nat_trans : n m p,
  beq_nat n m = true
  beq_nat m p = true
  beq_nat n p = true.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 3 stars, advanced (split_combine)

We proved, in an exercise above, that for all lists of pairs, combine is the inverse of split. How would you formalize the statement that split is the inverse of combine? When is this property true?
Complete the definition of split_combine_statement below with a property that states that split is the inverse of combine. Then, prove that the property holds. (Be sure to leave your induction hypothesis general by not doing intros on more things than necessary. Hint: what property do you need of l1 and l2 for split combine l1 l2 = (l1,l2) to be true?)

Definition split_combine_statement : Prop
  (* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH   := _your_definition_ . *) . Admitted.

Theorem split_combine : split_combine_statement.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 3 stars, advanced (filter_exercise)

This one is a bit challenging. Pay attention to the form of your induction hypothesis.

Theorem filter_exercise : (X : Type) (test : X bool)
                             (x : X) (l lf : list X),
     filter test l = x :: lf
     test x = true.
Proof.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 4 stars, advanced, recommended (forall_exists_challenge)

Define two recursive Fixpoints, forallb and existsb. The first checks whether every element in a list satisfies a given predicate:
      forallb oddb [1;3;5;7;9] = true

      forallb negb [false;false] = true

      forallb evenb [0;2;4;5] = false

      forallb (beq_nat 5) [] = true
The second checks whether there exists an element in the list that satisfies a given predicate:
      existsb (beq_nat 5) [0;2;3;6] = false

      existsb (andb true) [true;true;false] = true

      existsb oddb [1;0;0;0;0;3] = true

      existsb evenb [] = false
Next, define a nonrecursive version of existsb — call it existsb' — using forallb and negb.
Finally, prove a theorem existsb_existsb' stating that existsb' and existsb have the same behavior.

(* FILL IN HERE *)